Category: Hume's fork


Here is the marvellous Kant plan. Sorry I haven’t added anything to it, but that’s your job! I’m too busy packing my life into boxes.

Advertisements

Kant believed that claims about the world could be both ‘synthetic‘ in that they could tell us something about the world that isn’t contained in their own terms, and ‘a priori‘ because they can be known independent of experience of the world. 


This is a response to Hume who had denied such a possibility. ‘Hume’s fork‘ (see previous entry) made a strict separation between synthetic propositions, which for him could only be known ‘a posteriori‘ and ‘analytic‘ propositions which could be known a priori, but told us nothing about the world that was not already contained in their terms. 

To understand this we have to look at the way the sentences we use to make propositions and claims about the world work. Sentences consist of subjects (the thing the sentence is about) and predicates (the words that say something about the subject). So, the sentence ‘Some frogs are green’ has ‘Some frogs’ as its subject and ‘are green’ as its predicate. 

Both Kant and Hume thought that ‘analytic‘ statements are those in which the subject contains the predicate and consequently they don’t add any information about the world: an example of this would be the sentence ‘green frogs are green’, or to push it a little further, ‘kangaroos are animals’, because we could claim that the concept of ‘kangaroo’ contains the concept of ‘animal’, so if we already have the concept of ‘kangaroo’ we already have the concept of ‘animal’ and we know this independent of (further) experience’, we know it ‘a priori

On the other hand the predicates of ‘synthetic‘ statements are not contained in the subject, so they do give us additional information about the world; for example ‘This frog is green’ or ‘this kangaroo has a stamp collection.’

But Kant thought that statements like ‘7 + 5 = 12’ were both ‘synthetic‘ and ‘a priori‘, in fact he thought that Mathematical judgments are all, without exception, synthetic.’ For Kant, there is nothing contained in the concept of ‘7’ and ‘5’  that makes the knowledge that that adding them together will result in ’12’ immediately obvious or unavoidable. What he was getting at is perhaps easier to see if we consider larger numbers like for example, 38976 and 45204; their sum 84180 certainly does leap out at me, but I’m v. poor at maths. I think this gives an inkling of what Kant meant, but an awful lot of reading is really required to work your way into his idea. 
Kant  also thought that science could come up with synthetic a priori statements. He claimed that the statement, ‘In all changes in the physical world the quantity of matter remains unchanged.’ was such an example; he said;

Now, in  thinking the concept of matter I do not think its permanence but only its presence in the space that it fills. Thinking that matter is permanent isn’t like thinking that women are female, or that tigers are animals. In judging that matter is permanent, therefore, I go beyond the concept of matter in order to add to it something that I didn’t think in it. So the proposition isn’t analytic but synthetic; yet it is thought a priori.

He also claimed that the statement, ‘When one body collides with another, action and reaction must always be equal‘ was synthetic and a priori

Again it is not obvious (not to most mortals anyway) exactly what he meant, but if we consider his ideas about the ‘categories‘: how we experience the world in the way we do because time, space and cause and effect are built in to the way our minds are set up to experience the world, then we begin to see how we might know ‘a priori’ the stuff above about action and reaction, and such ‘knowledge’ certainly seems to add to our information about the world and is therefore ‘synthetic‘. Hume, of course denied that ideas about cause and effect, action and reaction etc. were anything other than the product of experience and as such, although synthetic, could only be known ‘a posteriori’.

So, I hope that’s clear, now. Another Saturday afternoon bites the dust of metaphysical speculation. And I haven’t marked your essays yet!

We read Section 3 – 4, of David Hume’s  ‘Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding‘. It is the ‘billiard ball‘ bit and it’s about causation and inductive reasoning. 


The fact that these ideas seem counter intuitive (seems daft) is the whole point. Hume points out that ‘custom’ and ‘habit’ has a very strong grip on our ways of thinking and this is why we think there is a law or ‘principle’ of cause and effect operating in the physical world. 


What we need to grasp is the difference between: 

1. predicting that event ‘A’ will be followed by event ‘B’ just because it always has in the past


and 


2. believing we have uncovered a ‘law’ of the physical world that says event ‘A’ will always be followed by event ‘B’ regardless of the time, circumstances (and universe) that those events occur in. 


No one (certainly not Hume) is saying that we shouldn’t use our ability to predict and control the world through the knowledge we gain through experience, but we must not formulate laws based on what are always limited observations of ‘recurring phenomenal patterns’. In other words however many times you observe a billiard ball striking another it will never be enough to conclude or infer that the second ball will always move.


To do so would be to use induction or inductive reasoning. Induction works like this:


  • All the ice I have ever touched was cold, therefore all ice is cold. 

Or

  • All the one billion billiard balls struck with a cue moved, therefore all billiard balls move when struck with a cue. 

It is to taking particular events and making them the basis of universal laws. You might think this is daft, but even Stephen Hawking agrees! He says,

“No matter how many times the results of experiments agree with some theory, you can never be sure that the next time the result will not contradict the theory.” 


Finally we must be careful not to confuse induction with deduction. Wikipedia explains something like this:


Deductive reasoning, sometimes called deductive logic, is reasoning which uses deductive arguments to move from given statements (premises) to conclusions, which must be true if the premises are true.[1] An example of deductive reasoning, given by Aristotle, is

All men are mortal. (major premise)

Socrates is a man. (minor premise)

Socrates is mortal. (conclusion)


So, we can see that deductive reasoning moves from a general principle to a particular example, whereas inductive reasoning moves from a particular example to a general principle.